Few issues lead to such apparently inconsistent positions as does the death penalty. Much of the "pro-life" community, for example, is staunchly pro-death in this context. As a criminal defense lawyer, I might be expected to categorically oppose capital punishment; under circumstances where culpability is beyond doubt, however, I have no problem with it at all, but for reasons other than those you might expect.Helmut's comments (edited slightly for grammar from the original):
It's well established that the death penalty is not a deterrent. I would argue that it's not even a penalty. And if it's neither a deterrent nor a penalty, what's the point? Follow my reasoning, here.
First, I approach the question from my own atheistic point of view. Death is nothing more than the permanent termination of consciousness. Once one's consciousness has been terminated, there can be no punishment, no joy, no amusement, no irritation, no nothing. By this reasoning, the death "penalty" is actually an end to the awareness that one is being punished, or, in other words, the premature end of punishment. If Mr. Killer is jailed on Tuesday and executed on Wednesday, he's only been punished for one day, after which his consciousness is humanely and mercifully extinguished. That doesn't strike me as particularly penal. I suspect that most people, when presented with a hypothetical choice between 40 years in a penitentiary and a swift, painless demise, would at least give serious consideration to the "easy way out", with emphasis on the word easy.
But most people do not share my godless take on things, so my argument must address the majority view. In the Christian tradition, there is an afterworld. Those who have accepted Jesus as their Lord and savior are admitted to Heaven, an eternal paradise. Now the various sects of Christianity have various means by which a sinner can be admitted to heaven. Baptism by immersion, confession and absolution, whatever. Even the most evil baby-raping murderer can enjoy Eternal Bliss, if he does what is necessary. If Mr. Killer has complied with the requirements, he attains paradise immediately after riding the spike. Again, not particularly penal.
Let's suppose, however, that our subject's crimes were so gross, so heinous, that even God can't forgive them. And to make matters worse, he's proud of his crimes, and professes an eagerness to commit even more and more egregious offenses. In such a case, Hell looms as the ultimate punishment. The doomed will spend eternity roasting on the coals and being tortured by Satan and his legions of lesser imps and demons.
"Aha!", says the pro-death Christian. "That's the ticket!" Or is it?
Eternity is a long, long time. And if we execute Mr. Killer at age 30, we've only added about 40 years to his torment. Do the math; 40 years is an incalculably, infinitesimally small percentage of eternity. It doesn't even equal the percentage of an ocean represented by a single molecule of water! By executing Mr. Killer, we have only increased his damnation by an amount too small to measure.
Life imprisonment, on the other hand, will consume 100% of the damned's Earthly life, during which time he may contemplate the horrible fate which awaits him. Consequently, such a fate imposes decades of temporal punishment on the criminal, followed by eternal punishment on his immortal soul. QED, the death penalty is less penal than life imprisonment.
As life imprisonment is more penal than death, it should be the preferred mode of punishing the worst among us. It has the additional benefits of allowing for correcting for racial bias in capital cases and righting the occasional wrongful conviction. Furthermore, the expense of keeping prisoners fed, clothed and housed for life is a small percentage of our total corrections budget. There is an economy of scale at work here. We could more than make up for it by not imprisoning people for possessing small amounts of marijuana, for example.
Now, you may argue that the death penalty serves other functions, such as providing "closure" to the victims and their families, or quenching our species' unique thirst for revenge. Well, that's fine. But the justice system doesn't exist to provide psychological remedies for the wronged, and in many states (including mine) the "closure" afforded by the death "penalty" is not available anyway, under any circumstances. So, let's drop the pretense that we're punishing anyone by executing them. If we're satisfying our bloodlust, let's just say so. And if we're not willing to say so, then we shouldn't be doing it.
I like this. The novel part is looking at the nature of "penalty," rather than justifications for punishment as social policy. Most philosophical arguments tend to consider the policy of capital punishment (CP) in terms of the broader society – a crime is a crime precisely because it harms others and, ostensibly, society as a whole. You're thinking about the actual penalty phase of the individual criminal by dropping the effect of CP on possible deterrence of would-be criminals. So, you move to a retributive-type argument.
To be pedantic, the main arguments in philosophy re CP come from three theoretical positions: that CP is/is not a deterrent in society regarding possible future crimes (future-oriented); that CP is/is not retribution for the crime already committed (past-oriented); that CP is wrong because criminals ought to and can undergo rehabilitation in which the punishment and motivation for rehabilitation stem from exclusion from society. [MT mentions the rehab issue]. All three are complicated further by the practical issue that CP is, in actual society, distributed unjustly according to race and means, and that the criminal justice system is fallible and, worse, often prosecutes erroneously and unjustly.
I tend to think, simply, that the latter consideration is good enough to get rid of CP. If somehow problems of both inequality and proof were overcome, I'd have to rethink this position. But it's good enough for me for now.
In your argument, there’s a tacking between deterrence and retributive views, and I think this is because you’ve constructed the argument to be directed at a specific audience: Christian pro-life, pro-CP people. Rehabilitative arguments often come from religious thinkers, for instance, but you’re looking at only those Christians making retributive claims. The idea behind retribution can take the form of eye for an eye (lex talionis) or the less religious Kantian view that the crime of murder is a kind of opting out of a society in which the Golden Rule applies (or categorical imperatives against using human beings as means, etc.). CP completes the opt-out. Case closed. The tack re deterrence is that belief in a miserable next few decades functions as more of a deterrent than death, whether one believes in an afterlife or one is an atheist.
In psychological terms, I'm not sure how much it matters if a criminal is executed after one day in prison or five years. Five years (and appeals, etc.) may actually engender hope that he'll see out his natural years for a criminal who fears death. Only the God-fearing criminal would fear hell/God – and that may actually be a deterrent for would-be criminals in the first place, as long as they're genuine believers. Tough to prove, though, in the absence of those hypothetical criminals. So, the psychological element may satisfy the religious person seeking CP for a criminal (retribution), but it’s unclear what effect it has on the criminal himself. In deterrence terms, knowing that one could be executed the following day after conviction could actually be more horrifying to the criminal and/or potential criminal, without resorting to the atheism-or-believer case. But framing the discussion in this way assumes that the "penalty" part of CP is terror at the prospect of death, not the death itself (and this is a deterrence argument).
I can see the merits of your move – it’s a sort of deconstructive critique of an inconsistent religious view. But I don’t know how much it extends to a broader argument against CP as criminal justice policy. For one thing, it grants Christians their most mythical beliefs as the basis for the argument and then builds a reductio out of those beliefs. The problem is that one has to grant them in the first place.
2 comments:
If the death penalty is not a deterrent, explain for me why Michael Moore is not dead and I am not on death row.
Maybe you're a coward, or afraid of life in prison, or you can't find a way to make the benefits outweigh the costs, or you hold onto norms of retributive justice, or you think that murder is simply wrong, or....
Post a Comment